An Automatic Submachinegun Commentary on Jang-gya's Harmony of Emptiness
and Dependent-Arising in the Middle Way Consequence School
By Achmed el'Hamster
(REL 526; 12/8/87)
An Exhibition of How Not to Write a Serious Term Paper;
We Apologize for All Syntactic, Logical and Factual Problems in the Below
Essay in Advance
Table of Contents
Introduction
The Self of Negation
Dependent Arising
Emptiness
Comparison to Contemporary Western and other
Views
One Sided Conversation
Notes
Bibliography
Introduction
The purpose of this aptly named essay is to procure
another viewpoint on the text of Jang-gya's presentation of emptiness.
This is hopefully going to be something beyond a mere transformation of
Jang-gya's ideas into another form of words, but will be a further insight
into their meaning. Jang-gya presents his text for the purpose of
generating insight into emptiness in the reader. This is not to say
that the reader will comprehend emptiness completely or cognize it directly
when he has finished reading, but will have a wedge between himself and
his old ideas of reified or inherent existence. This promotion of
separation from viewing objects as existing in their own right, or from
their own side, is something which very few Western philosophical systems
have a handle on. A contemporary Western attempt to grasp emptiness
occurs in Robert Anton Wilson's The Illuminati Papers, a treatise
on how to reprogram one's brain. This attempt is the realization
that all sciences are really 'neuro'-sciences, or that they do not really
study an external world, but study the way the mind perceives this external
world to operate.1 One of the recent trends among scientists
is to use Eastern ideas to understand such topics as Quantum Physics.
It seems that the systems of religion and life philosophy engendered in
the East may also be applicable to the scientific knowledge of the West.
The most appealing aspect of Jang-gya's system
for myself is the emphasis on the use of reasoned arguments to remove one's
incorrect ideas. This seems to be more accessible to the person who
is used to rational thought, such as the aforementioned scientists, and
might have the methodology that they would be looking for in a religious
system--a methodology that commonly practiced Christianity could be said
to lack. The air-tight argument that "God is all knowing, all powerful,
unchanging, and not subject to human understanding" is fine for those who
do not wish to breathe, but it has no attraction for me. Far better
is the reasoning approach to insight into existence, where one's intellect
can be put into use instead of lobotomized.
Jang-gya's reputation as a physicist not withstanding,
the understanding of Emptiness is seen as an aid to one in the much larger
problem of liberation (compared to problem of the location of an electron,
as in Quantum). Only those who are deeply based in an understanding
of the selflessness of persons and phenomena can be liberated from cyclic
existence, in Jang-gya's and the 'mainstream' Consequentialist's view.
This differs from other systems of Buddhism, in that they attempt to refute
permanence of self in different ways, and do not necessarily refute a self
of phenomena. For example, the mind-only school refutes the difference
in entity between subject and object, while the Sutra school only refutes
a self of persons designated by a false status.2 These
other, 'lower' schools claim that the Consequentialists fall to the depths
of nihilism that Nagarjuna warns of: "Through [the view of] no [nominal]
existence there is nothing but cyclic existence".3 Of
course, the Consequentialists claim that the other schools are still trapped
in cyclic existence because they are still positing some sort of real existence,
as Nagarjuna also warns against: "Through [the view of inherent] existence
one is not released".4 For lack of space and time, I will
attempt to stick to an analysis of the Prasangikas of Jang-gya's sort.
Emptiness itself is said to be the mode of
subsistence of (all) phenomena, because of the reason of dependent arising.
Objects and persons arise through causes and conditions, and as such are
said not to exist from their own side in some separate way. Also,
objects are imputed (by an imputational or designating consciousness) in
dependence on their collection of parts.5 This means that
they are not only dependent on what they 'are', but also upon the consciousness
viewing these objects (way past our ideas of physics really being neuro-physics,
or neurosurgery really being neuro-neurosurgery). Dependent arising
is a positive phenomenon. It is something occurring in your mind
right now; the dots of ink on this sheet are being transformed into words
and then into mental images in dependence on the shape of the dots.
There aren't really any words on the paper you are holding, because words
are in your mind. In that way, the words on the page are empty of
inherent existence, although that is certainly not the only way they are
empty. They are also empty, because there is no one gist or meaning
or way of grokking this paper. A word could have a slightly or vastly
different meaning to every person who reads it, especially in dependence
on the words surrounding it. If every person understands a word differently,
then every sentence is understood differently, and there can be no claim
about the meaning of the collection of words. If everyone reading
it gets a different meaning, how can it be inherently existent, meaning
something from its own side? With these reasonings, one can see that
emptiness is somehow the flip side of dependent arising. Emptiness
proposes nothing in the place of inherent existence, and in this way it
is non-affirming. It is also a negative, or a negation. It
is simply the negative, or negating of, the idea that something is existent
from its own side or inherently existent. Emptiness is existent in
the sense that it can be realized, but it does not exist as a thing.
I cannot truthfully in my meditations come to a stage where I can say,
"This is emptiness". I can realize the emptiness of something, and
even all things, but not label anything emptiness without falling back
into designational conception, or the normal (innate) mode of perceiving.
One certainly does not usually think to himself,
"this object is inherently existent and exists from its own side", but
one does assent to this appearance without realizing he is doing so.
One goes along with the way things appear without giving it any active
thought at all, usually. Having a strong feeling that some things
really exist, that they have their own existence without needing us to
be involved in any way, is the gateway to believing in things as inherently
existent. Strengthening that feeling to the level of actually actively
seeing oneself and objects as inherently existent is difficult, and suffers
from many internal inconsistencies when given sufficient thought.
If we can at least cut through this exaggerated level of thought that reinforces
this erroneous idea of the "self" of persons and objects, then we may be
able to attack the subtler forms of this delusion as well.
Prasangas (consequences) are extremely useful
in cutting to the marrow of the internally inconsistent view. Instead
of standing on some unsupported ground and trying to force one's viewpoint
on an opponent, as perhaps in a syllogism, one is using the opponents own
vocabulary and ideas as the support for a position the opponent can absolutely
not agree with, because it runs counter to his direct experience.
For example, in some non-Buddhist meditations, one may pick something as
the ultimate truth to meditate on, something that one believes is inherently
existent, unchanging and not subject to designation by an imputational
consciousness. God is often considered to be this, or Brahman, the
Tao, or perhaps even the Buddha Nature (Tathagathagarbha) by some Chinese
schools of Buddhism.
If one does reason regarding the nature of
God, and does not escape into self-fulfilling rationalizations (e.g. God
is unknowable), one would find that, if one really likes the idea of a
God and doesn't want him to evaporate due to not being inherently existent,
it is not necessary that he be inherently existent, nor is it possible
from the accepted writings about him. God created the world, and
this means he created; to create is to have an idea and to change {what
exists} into {what exists plus the creation}. Between the idea and
the completion, there is mental change as the creation occurs. There
is also a change in the energies exerted before beginning to create and
after beginning, which means that whatever method God used to create the
world required change in him, showing that either he is teaching incorrect
things about himself or he is not changeless, and therefore not inherently
existent (or one can try to reclaim the idea that he made something in
his own image that was too stupid to understand itself or him). To
lose the non-thinking assent with ideas of inherent existence is important
to understanding emptiness fully, and even high flights of reasoning into
strengthening ideas of inherent existence will eventually lead to a better
understanding of emptiness. I found this to be very true when I was
writing the One Sided Conversation. Sometimes
to find the emptiness of the conversational situation, I had to first understand
the wrong view as well as I could and attempt to believe it before I was
able to understand why it was empty.
Emptiness can be considered to be the central
philosophical issue of Buddhism, and the direct realization of it to be
the major religious goal. The Consequentialists put a lot of stock
in it, anyway. A deeper delving into the various issues of emptiness
follows in the next several sections. These hope to explain in closer
detail the concepts involved. The sections after that are comparisons
of other systems of thought, which hope to give different angles of approach
to these details, and afford the reader a holographic mental image of what
it is to follow the Consequence school of Buddhism. [And then there's
the One Sided Conversation to bulk out the paper a bit.]
The Self of Negation
Selflessness, in the Consequence school, is understood
as the idea that when one searches for a self-powered self for either a
phenomenon or a person, one will find nothing that is this self
among the basis of designation of the object or outside of the basis.
The basis of designation is what makes an object or a person distinguishable
from other objects or persons; the characteristics that can be said to
be conventionally part of it. Upon seeking the self of the person
or object, one will only find the conventional idea that there is a self,
and will not find anything that really IS undeniably that self. Selflessness
is actually a negating of the inherently existent self, not an attempt
to negate the phenomena that we perceive. As Chandrakirti says: "Here,
'self' is an inherent nature of phenomena, that is, a non-dependence on
another."6 It might seem at times, to the confused reader
who is not familiar with Buddhist psycho-babble, that Jang-gya is trying
to say that there is no person or phenomenon at all. For example,
Jang-gya says:
If one is not satisfied with mere nominalities and enters into searching
to find the object imputed in the expression 'form', [trying to discover]
whether it can be taken as color, shape, some other factor, or the collection
of all these, and so forth, one will not find anything, and all presentations
[of phenomena] will be impossible.7
This would seem to say that there is no object (or no 'form', where 'form'
serves as a variable holding the name of some object) to be found.
What he really means is still consistent, however. He is trying to
find some sort of 'form' that stands by itself, but there is none.
None in the basis of designation, none outside of the basis of designation.
Seven-fold Reasoning
The refutation of this self is accomplished through
a variety of reasonings. The major reasoning for refuting a self
of persons is the Seven-fold Reasoning. This reasoning attempts to
confront every possibility of an inherently existent object, and by showing
that they all are impossible, show that an inherently existent object is
impossible. For example, one could try to find his self's existence
by looking for himself:
-
as being one with his basis of designation,
-
as being inherently different from his basis,
-
as being inherently dependent on his basis,
-
as being something on which his basis depends inherently,
-
as inherently possessing his basis,
-
as being the mere collection of his basis,
-
or as being the mere shape of his basis.8
Each of these ideas is refuted in a different way...
The 'I' is not one with its basis of designation
(1), because when one says 'I am tired,' he does not mean that his pinkie
is tired, he usually means his brain is tired of thinking or his body is
tired of moving. Just having these two different types of tired associated
with the I shows that the I is not always held to be one with the full
totality of the basis of designation. Also, if the I inherently exists
and is one with the basis of designation, then, because the basis of designation
is mind and body, the I would be twain, or the reverse that since the I
is one, the mind and body are only one, and have no parts.
The I cannot be inherently different from
its basis of designation (2), because then there could be no connection
from the I to the basis of designation, or in other words, your mind would
not be related to you at all. It is surely hard to fathom how 'you'
could exist inherently separate from your mind and body.
The I is not inherently dependent upon its
basis (3), because the basis changes, and therefore the I would change
(and not be inherently existent), nor can the basis of designation depend
inherently upon the I (4), for then it could not change due to being based
on something that exists inherently (and it does change).
The I can further be seen not to inherently
possess its parts (5), because to possess means to have as property, to
own or to have as an attribute. If the inherently existent I owns
the basis of designation, what happens to a chopped off finger? Does
'I' still own it, or does the basis of designation change to reflect the
lack of finger (thereby changing the property or attributes of I, which
cannot change). If it does continue to own the finger, and a squirrel
runs off with it and builds it into its nest, does the I then own the squirrel's
nest? Eventually the finger will rot and deteriorate into nothing,
be incorporated in the earth or other beings, and cease to resemble anything
like the finger it used to. This is just expanding the statement
that the inherently existent I cannot possess the basis of designation,
because the basis is subject to change.
The I cannot be the mere collection of the
basis of designation (6), because if it were, it would be merely a label
for something that already exists, and would not be anything different
or interesting. Also it is clear that the mere collection changes,
and an inherently existent mere collection could not. It would also
be non-sensical to claim "I have a stomach ache," because you would be
the stomach ache.
The seventh (and thankfully final) reasoning
is to see that the I is not merely the shape of its basis of designation
(7). For if it were, the shape can change, and therefore the I would
change. I can bend my arm to change its shape, but I don't feel my
self is changing because of this.
These explanations of the Seven-fold Reasoning
are certainly not meant to be complete, or to be any kind of finalized
statement on how to use the Reasoning, but are merely meant as a clue into
how one can proceed along through the Seven folds and refute inherent existence.
Negation of Inherent Production
The main reasoning for challenging a self of phenomena
is the refutation of production from the four extremes. These also
are an attempt to produce a hermetic set that covers all possibilities
of inherently existent production, for it is assumed that for something
to exist inherently it must have been inherently produced. If it
was not inherently produced, then it does not exist, for no conventional
production could manufacture an inherently existent object. The four
extremes of production are causeless production, production from self,
production from other, and production from both self and other. For
one to discover a possibility outside of this set, one has only to think
up a method of production that is not contained within these. I can't
think of any, so I will go on to explain these four methods.
Causeless production means that the inherently
existent object has been produced from no causes whatsoever, and nothing
that is a cause can have contributed to its production. This seems
unreasonable just hearing about it, for all things are seen to have some
cause. This is along the lines that there are some things that happen
just because they do, like accidents and natural disasters. Surely
though, this is only when looked at from a limited perspective. If
you were out driving, and had an accident, you helped to cause it by being
out driving in the first place. You are not completely cause free.
Even something as immaterial as the space between the galaxies is caused
by the galaxies being there to allow you to label the space. The
most difficult thing I can think up to refute is that God is produced causelessly,
just from his own nature. God is not produced from anything, God
produces everything else. Whew, what did he do before he had we little
beings to play with anyway? I see no way of refuting his causeless
production, although I can easily see that he is not inherently existent
if he conventionally produces. A reasoning that might work for someone
who believes that God is causeless is thus; if God is produced causelessly
then there is no reason for God. If there is no reason for God, then
there can be no reason for us, because we have been produced by God.
Therefore, everything should be produced causelessly, while we can see
that it is not, and we would have no cause for anything, while we do have
causes.
Refuting a production from self requires a
further analysis of what the self is, and how it would produce itself.
If something produced itself, when would it not exist? If it did
not exist, then it could not produce itself from nothing, could it?
If it did exist, then when it was not manifest, where was it? How
can an object somehow go back in time to produce itself for the time that
it is existent now? The Samkhya's would say that I obviously do not
understand their position, and that when the object is unmanifest, the
continuum still exists and the parts that go toward constructing whatever
the object is are unmanifest 'object'. Let us choose elevator music,
for example. The music produces itself somehow, even though it is
being played over a speaker, and is transmitted over a wire, and originally
is being played on a compact disc player (maybe)? All of these objects
are unmanifest music? What happens to the music if I break the speaker
cone, and there is no more music? Is the silence generated by this
produced from itself, with the now non-manifest music being part of its
entity, and therefore the music is also unmanifest silence? And if
I remember the silence so well, because it was a blissful change from the
music, then the silence was unmanifest memory, and so on and so on.
It would seem then, that since any object has so many contributing factors
that are hidden from the observer (i.e. motion of the earth, slight electromagnetic
field, etc.), then basically everything is unmanifest everything else.
This is harder to understand than dependent arising! It also seems
that since the music produced itself once, then I could never have turned
it off, if it was a substantial entity that had already managed to produce
itself from its own side. There is much more room in this argument
for understanding the gaps between existent effect, and unmanifest effect,
and between the effect and its own production from itself, but I'm already
stuck trying to posit production from self at all.
The production from other is refuted through
understanding that an other must be an inherently other phenomenon.
This other is so different from the effect, that it is inherently different
from it. This means that each stands alone from its own side.
Now, if each stands alone from its own side, how can it possibly be that
they are related at all? How can the inherently other cause contribute
anything to the effect at all? If it could in some way be linked
as having served to produce the effect, then it would not be inherently
other. Therefore there is no production from other. And once
we have ascertained that production from self and production from other
cannot occur, it seems that suggesting that objects are produced from both
is only adding the problems of both together. If it is produced from
something inherently other, there is still the problem that the other cannot
contribute to the effect, even though the effect produces itself as well.
These explanations of the self of negation
represent my basic level of understanding selflessness. I make no
claim at being the master of these concepts with such ability that I could
teach others; it is only through my attempts to expound them to help others
that I really see my own progress, and perhaps understand my own selflessness
better.
Dependent Arising
Dependent Arising is seen as the supporting condition
for selflessness and emptiness. If one really understood dependent
arising, would it be sufficient for liberation? If this understanding
is of an ultimate sort, then probably, for "the two extremes are cleared
away by this reasoning [of dependent arising]". But it is also said
that one must understand that things (and persons) are empty of inherent
existence to obtain liberation, and it does seem that one could still reify
existence, or posit inherent existence, even if he understood dependent
arising well (perhaps just by not thinking of the appearance to which he
is assenting).
Dependent Arising can be said to be the meaning
of Emptiness or vice-versa, but this is only verbal play, and contributes
nothing to the grasp of either. Emptiness is 'proved' by Dependent
Arising however, as the Questions of Sagaramati Sutra says: "Those
which arise dependently are free of inherent existence".9
To be free of inherent existence is to be empty.
Dependent Arising is more than just the obvious
idea that objects depend on causes for their existence and continuation,
but is also the 'immersion' in this idea, which is achieved through fully
realizing the links of everything to every other thing. A grain of
sand dropping on Earth does have an effect on the thoughts of a being on
a planet revolving around Alpha Centauri, even just from the gravitational
attraction between the sand and the creatures physical thought mechanism
components. A small relation certainly, but they are not completely
independent, especially if there is a stronger causal link, e.g. that grain
of sand is the last in an hourglass timing when an explosion is going to
take place in the Centauran's dwelling. Things may be related in
ways that are not obvious at first.
Certainly, all things are dependently arisen
from a personal perspective. You have to notice them to include them
in your cognitive continuum, and they are dependent on this noticing in
the first place. Not only that, they are dependent for their designation
upon what collection of whatevers is designated. A basis of designation
for a cow is dependent on the parts of the cow, the sound of a cow, etc.
And they are also dependent upon what has caused them to occur, the factors
that have allowed the objects to come into being. A cow is dependent
upon its mother, its father, its birth, all of the food it has ever eaten,
all of the water that has for a while been part of it, and on and on.
Dependent arising and emptiness are perceived
simultaneously by the most evolved being, and do not conflict in the least.
They can be realized together for the best effect, because the understanding
of emptiness can be seen to counteract the view of inherent existence (although
dependent arising can perform this function as well), and the understanding
of dependent arising can be seen to counteract the nihilistic view that
nothing exists (which some people might mistake the existence of emptiness
to imply). In this way, dependent arising and emptiness are seen
to be aiming towards the same focus.
Emptiness
Well, to this point it seems almost like the whole
paper is about emptiness anyway, and I could just stop where I am.
I unfortunately don't have the sense to do this, and would like to further
explore some ideas that are relevant to emptiness itself (or lack thereof).
Emptiness is a non-affirming negative for at least one reason; inherent
existence is considered a conception that ties one to cyclic existence.
If one is trying to remove this misconception, then one is basically trying
to find an antidote to a problem. In going to a healer for an antidote,
one is not given another disease (for the most part). And this I
consider to reveal something about emptiness, for if we are trying to obtain
liberation from cyclic existence and we are tied to cyclic existence by
a misconception, why would we want another conception? If emptiness
proposed something that was Emptiness in terms of being something label-able,
then would we not have just another idea that has replaced inherent existence
for us? I see this as a possible tie to something like cyclic existence,
perhaps empty existence. Instead, emptiness cuts our chains when
we understand it fully, and is not laying on furred handcuffs of further
mind-occupations, because emptiness itself is empty, and is not inherently
existent.
Also, the mind that cognizes emptiness is
not seen as losing anything but a misconception. Emptiness is not
a cause for one's understanding of dependent arising to evaporate, only
nihilism is. Cause and effect are still posited in the conventional
sense, and a goal is to be able to cognize the emptiness of an object with
all senses opened to its apparent self, but with none being fooled into
assenting to the appearance of the object, while still being able to posit
conventional cause and effect. This idea causes resonation, in my
mind at least, with the way I would consider a Buddha to perceive.
Emptiness also should never be seen as something
depressing or disenheartening. It is because things are empty that
change is possible. It is only when the mind is stuck on the bad
view of inherent existence that heart is lost. "Oh, I'll never change,
never be better, I can't rise above my nature" are strength-sapping ideas
to assert, and are very wrong as to the basic nature of a human as well.
A Buddha would not be possible, were things not empty, and there luckily
was a Buddha, further showing emptiness because of his ability to change,
to progress, to reach enlightenment.
Comparisons to Contemporary Western and Other
Views
Edward Conze:
In his section on The Three Doors to Deliverance,
Conze immediately sets my teeth on edge by stating, "the more important
a Buddhist doctrine, the less readily intelligible it generally is."10
This I feel is a somewhat insulting statement that could easily be misconstrued
as saying that the things Buddhists hold dear are the most irrational ideas
that they have presented. Trying to recover from this, I read his
definition of emptiness as the absence of something. Emptiness is
"that which is 'devoid of a self, or of anything belonging, or pertaining,
to a self (attaniya)'."11 This seems to be a different
view of emptiness than Jang-gya's, to whom emptiness is the absence of
inherent existence, or absence of a self. This seems to be saying that
emptiness is a particular thing devoid of a self, and not an attribute
to things, which is that they are empty of inherent existence. Conze
makes another conceivably derogatory remark, "logically, the term had not
been thought out very well."12 Perhaps further analysis
would help Conze to understand emptiness so that it might be logically
sensible to him.
Conze then later shows his difference from
Jang-gya's position by stating: "Things are 'empty' in the sense that they
are unsubstantial or unsatisfactory."13 The unsubstantial
Jang-gya would agree with, because things are ultimately not as they appear,
but I don't think that he thought of them as unsatisfactory in the way
that Conze speaks of. Conze is almost suggesting a whining Buddhist,
one who is just so unsatisfied by things that he calls them all unsatisfactory.
By their very nature, things are unsatisfactory and non-lasting, but this
was not the slant I received from Conze. He also states that "what
is 'empty' should be forsaken as worthless; as a result of treating it
for what it is, one is then liberated from it."14 It follows
that devotional action and love should not be practiced because they are
empty. This is not what I see Jang-gya saying at all. I believe
Conze is reading in his Western ideas that what is empty is useless and
devoid of value, and am pleased that this reaction is so easily showing--it
resembles the reaction to me of the early Chinese Buddhists to emptiness,
and isn't in the historical realm, it's almost currently occurring.
Conze's Christian slant is revealed throughout the article, as when he
talks of emptiness in the connotation of salvation15 rather
than of liberation. He does have several good points, such as "meditation
on 'emptiness' serves the purpose of helping us to get rid of this world
by removing the ignorance which binds us to it."16 I would
not say that Jang-gya is trying to get rid of the world, but if world were
to be a term denoting the wrong views of the world, then this is exactly
Jang-gya's point. What I see to be happening with Conze is the mutation
of Buddhism to fit the concepts of the people it comes into contact with,
as it historically did to the Bonist traditions of Tibet. Each new
proto-Buddhist understands as much as he can in terms of his current religion,
and begins to understand more (hopefully) as he pursues acquaintance with
the Dharma.
Jacques May:
This article I found to be extremely interesting,
seeing as how it is a double language translation at times. May manages
to translate some of the scriptures into French, and then transport this
understanding into English as well. May mentions many points which
coincide with what I perceive as Jang-gya's views, as in his explanation
of the Middle Way as not "clinging to any extreme,"17 and the
attempt not to fall to either substantialism (inherent existence) or nihilism.
I found his relation of Professor Lamotte's six major Madhyamika theses
to be revealing, and he here shows his wisdom in not asserting that the
Madhyamikas have no theses, although he is not talking specifically of
the Consequentialists. I had trouble determining whether May was
dealing mainly with the Consequentialists or Autonomists, and perhaps he
is not making any difference between them. He at times does seem
to be referring to Consequentialists, but I will just use his designation
of Madhyamika. He also realizes that the Madhyamika's are often required
"to deny [their] being nihilists"18 and the lack of "independent
existence, of a 'self-being' or 'own-being'(svabhava)"19 is
something the Madhyamikas assert.
May does seem to differ from Jang-gya's ideas
in a few ways, as when he states that "substantial existence" is the "only
form of existence which can really be called existence,"20 and
fails to posit conventional existence, which can be called existence.
He also says that "Emptiness...almost amounts to nothingness,"21
a phrase that I am sure would turn Jang-gya's stomach. The word emptiness
certainly is almost nothing, but the concept to be recognized is not nothing,
and realization of emptiness is not cognition of nothingness (in my understanding
of Jang-gya's position). He does at least throw in a slightly apologetic
sounding "Emptiness is not nothingness," but then qualifies his meaning
by saying "Madhyamika is a 'quasi-nihilism'".22 Surely
this is a lining of the hamster cage with hundred dollar bills in the way
that it seems to miss the true import of emptiness.
May also does seem to ignore the fact that
he has presented six Madhyamika theses earlier, and he states that "it
nowhere states a positive doctrine of being."23 This is
actually reasonable for he really is only saying that the Madhyamikas do
not assert something to replace the nature of reality that emptiness is
negating. He is not making the mistake of saying that Madhyamikas
have no theses, until he does say "the Madhyamika has no thesis of his
own, or more generally speaking, no philosophical position,"24
which does not allow that although one's views are empty, they can still
be held as views. I think that the idea that guides him toward thinking
this is that a philosophy for him has to somehow be thought of in the mind
of the philosophizer as 'more real' than anything else, so that it has
the right to talk about anything. Then May looks at this 'more real'
as being an inherently existent real. This is not a necessary quality
for one's own philosophical view; I feel it is just his view on philosophy.
May also states "the law of causality is both
necessary and impossible at the same time,"25 and he misses
that dependent arising is linked directly to emptiness, because he determines
that causality is impossible with "ontologically unsubstantial"26
causes and effects. But May does understand that without Emptiness,
the world would be impossible due to its having an inherently existent
nature and that it would get "torn apart into discrete entities helplessly
isolated," or would sink "down into chaos."27
May produces many ideas that are concordant
with Jang-gya's, but many of them also seem to be in contradiction.
This could arise from many factors, such as my flawed interpretations of
his translation into English or his flawed interpretations of his own translation,
or his just not having analyzed exactly the same Middle Way Consequence
School interpretation that I have.
Tenzin Gyatso (14th Dalai Lama):
I read a bit of this book without too much hope
of finding differences between Jang-Gya's and Gyatso's interpretations,
seeing as how they are from the same school. I did gain new understanding
of emptiness realization and the problems of labelling it, and so forth.
Other than that, I'm just using it as a reference I suppose, and even though
I have no contrasts per se, I did at least read through trying to find
something to talk about, other than just quoting the whole text and saying
that all this agrees with Jang-gya.28
Aaron K. Koseki:
This is the interesting article that tries to
settle the troubling vegetable enlightenment problem. I tried to
sidestep this issue when reading the article, and just pick out some interesting
things that pertain to Jang-gya's ideas. Koseki does a good job of
explaining how Buddha-Nature is not inherently existent in the sense that
the Consequentialists mean, "because inherent means 'what will come about'
"29 and does not mean inherent in the sense that it stands on
its own. The idea that Buddha-Nature was inherently existent is one
problem that I did not like in the treatises I have read, and I was glad
to come across this particular explanation, even if it is not what the
other Buddha-nature writers mean. The rest of Koseki's article dealt
with Buddha-nature in the main, and I, perhaps foolishly, proceeded to
other articles for more on emptiness.
Peter N. Gregory:
This is a good example of how I would not write
an article about Buddhism. Gregory is an artist at using exactly
the word he wants, but some of his words were not in my vocabulary or dictionary.
I did struggle to pierce this veil of non-comprehension, and did get a
bit out of the article. His explanation of Prasangika ultimate truth
I will quote at length because I thought it was such a clever way of hiding
what one is trying to say:
For the Prasangikas, ultimate truth is ineffable because there can
be no dichotomous discrimination in the apprehension of the ultimate nature
of reality, which ineluctably defies all attempts to verbalize or conceptualize
its essence. Since it can never be hypostatized in language, any
teaching which uses positive modes of locution must be qualified by an
explanation. The only kind of teaching which, in Thurman's words,
"does not require such an interpretation is that which is absolutely negative,
and absolute negation in the logical sense of only negating its negandum
without establishing or implying anything else." Thus, only those
teachings which adhere to a thoroughgoing apophasis are definitive(nitartha).30
This I feel is stretching the bounds of the common vocabulary a bit, but
I feel it is a nice gesture to translate the normal meanings into the language
of the intellectuals, so that even they have their chance at Buddhahood.
In order to help add to the understanding of the Consequential viewpoint,
I have translated this back into the common jargon:
For the Prasangika's, ultimate truth cannot be put into words, because
the very nature of ultimate truth is beyond words. Since it can never
be fully expressed in language, any teaching that is positively putting
something forth as being ultimate truth must include an explanation to
the effect of "The way that can be spoken of is not the constant way".31
The teachings that do not require this explanation are those that affirm
nothing and negate something, such as emptiness. Therefore, only
those teachings which promote a separation from the appearances of things
are ultimate.
I don't put this forth as any sort of Gospel, but just as what Gregory's
words mean to me.
Gregory does say something I found to be quite
different from Jang-gya's system, "The true understanding of emptiness,
therefore, entails the recognition that the other side of the tathagatagarbha's
being empty of all defiled dharmas is its being replete with infinite Buddha
dharmas."32 This does not seem to be the true understanding
of emptiness as Jang-gya has presented emptiness, and he would probably
say that the emptiness of the Tathagatagarbha is due to its not being inherently
existent.
Gregory has picked many examples that show
a contrast between Chinese Buddhism and Jang-gya's system, such as Tsung
Mi's claim: "Although he regarded the True Nature and its Marvelous Functioning
not to be non-existent, because he provisionally said they were non-existent,
[this teaching of emptiness] is called [one of] 'hidden intent'."33
I think Jang-gya would say that this is missing the point that
conventional reality is not non-existent, it is only empty of inherent
existence. Tsung Mi also asks, "If the mind and its objects are both
non-existent, then who is it that knows that they do not exist?"34
Well, the mind is only not inherently existent, and it would seem silly
to claim the mind does not exist at all, which is not what the Consequentialists
are doing. It seems that the main thrust of the Chinese Buddhists
is to not fall prey to the nihilism that they see expressed in the concept
of emptiness, just as the Consequentialists seek not to fall to nihilism
through the reasonings of dependent arising.
Minoru Kiyota:
This is the article I presented in class, and
I assume that it would be dull just to rehash my presentation, for the
reader who was in class at least. Hoping not to be a source of boredom,
I will at least explain something that has cleared in my mind since the
presentation. Before, I explained my not understanding a statement
of Kiyota's that true reality was "a realm of thought realized by denying
supremacy (paramartha) to phenomena, but affirming their conventionality,
and thus gaining insight into the essential identity of the two."35
This was due to my laboring under the misapprehension that Kiyota was saying
that phenomenal supremacy (inherent existence) was the same thing as conventional
existence. What I misunderstood was the order of the words, where
one denies phenomenal supremacy and affirms conventionality. I believe
the meaning Kiyota was trying to get across is that true reality was a
realm of thought realized by denying inherent existence, but still retaining
conventional appearances, and thus seeing their identity, in the sense
that conventional appearances prove that inherent existence is not existent
(because they change and are not inherently produced). This suggests
to me also the point in enlightened perception when one can cognize emptiness
and still retain the appearances of objects.
William L. Ames:
Ames is interested in thoroughly unraveling the
meaning of svabhava in Chandrakirti's texts. Although I could be
suffering from lack of insight, I found no things to contrast with Jang-gya's
position. Ames' ideas of what svabhava is are aligned with Jang-gya's,
in that they do not violate any qualities of dependent arising or emptiness.
Ames' explanation is also nice because it
recognizes that there are several different ways that svabhava is used,
from the 'true reality' idea of conventional existence, to the idea that
'true reality' is the fact that nothing has an ultimate nature.36
I found Ames' article to be a very helpful addition to the discussion of
svabhava in class, but not to be something for which I could find much
to disagree with, not that that was my only purpose in reading it.
Richard H. Robinson:
Robinson's article had me swaying between thinking
that the man was an idiot to thinking he was a genius, and then back to
thinking he was an idiot again. Part of the reason behind this was
his style of what I might call cocky insults, such as comparing Nagarjuna
to the master of a shell game at a country fair, and saying that there
is a sophistic trick behind Madhyamika reasonings.37 I
found his explanation of the 'standard mechanism' of Nagarjuna's resoning
also to be unsatisfactory, in that it did not seem to be an explanation
of a consequence, but rather a mathematical explanation of some idea in
group theory. Robinson does seem to have a convincing grasp of the
material from the sutras, and has a strong position for many of his arguments,
but I believe that he has lost the heart meaning of the reason to strive
toward understanding of emptiness, which is to be liberated from ignorant
views and to be liberated from cyclic existence. I don't really see
that he is speaking from a position of knowing why Nagarjuna proposes to
destroy ideas of inherent existence, which Robinsons calls svabhava, or
from believing that anyone has any ideas of things existing inherently.
It is good that he is at a level of realization where he sees through these
ideas, but perhaps not everyone is. However, I do think that Robinson
could profit from a realization of profound emptiness, and that it would
not really be just a delving into "axioms that are in variance with common
sense and [that are] not accepted by any known philosophy."38
Lao Tzu:
Although the Tao Te Ching was not on the reading
list, my mind had become so full of Consequences and different ways of
misunderstanding emptiness, that I had to resort to an old favorite to
see if Lao Tzu at least got anything straight with respect to emptiness,
for it would disappoint me if he had not. In the very first stanza,
I am reassured that Lao Tzu understood emptiness or at least the nature
of things well, for he says, "The way that can be spoken of is not the
constant way, the name that can be named is not the constant name."39
This is certainly not necessarily proposing an idea in place of spoken
names, but is negating the idea that something that can be talked about
is constant, or inherently existent. That is rather amazing, because
it is basically a non-affirming negative, much as emptiness is. Also,
Lao Tzu says, "These two are the same but diverge in name as they issue
forth."40 This immediately brings to my mind that cognizing
emptiness is non-dual understanding, because one can posit the emptiness
and the conventional appearances at the same time. I could go on
and on, and do an analysis of the Tao in Consequential terms, but that
would add extra body to an already huge paper. Therefore, I will
just add here that the links between Emptiness and the Tao are amazing,
although they may not be exactly identical whatever-they-are's.
One Sided Conversation
The following is a possible mono-dialogue between
myself and myself, one of me believing he is inherently existent, and one
slightly learned in the teachings of the Consequentialists. It could
also be a conversation between me and you who is reading this, or between
any one Consequentially minded person and any one person who holds he is
inherently existent.
Where are you? You don't exist as you
appear, because I remember you being different than you are now.
It could just be my senses, and probably is, except that you admit to moving,
do you not? Therefore, you change and do not exist as you appear.
So if there is an inherently existent you, where is it? Or even a
conventionally existent you? Let's try to find a conventionally existent
you that exists on its own. Is it your body? Then when you
are dead, you will still be you as much as you are now. I guess that
you could be a living body only, but then you would be pretty dull if you
had no mind. If you're just your brain, then that would be all you
need to exist, and you wouldn't have a sense of identity with your hands
at all. Are you your mind? If I cut off your head, not that
I would, you would still be the same? Your mind cannot function very
well with no body to be associated with, at least you admit this.
So perhaps you are your mind and body working together. This is not
quite right, because if you are the mere collection inherently, then there
are inherently two yous since the mind and body are two.
Oh, this is a conceptual difference and not
a real difference, right? The mind and body are seen as separate
only by deluded beings? Well, then inherently existent means pointably,
findably existent, right? Please point to your self. Well,
you just pointed to your stomach, which is in the mere collection, but
is it you? Oh, your head maybe is you, that's why you're pointing
there now. But if you are inherently the mere collection, point to
that mere collection, stop pointing at parts within it. You see that
you have been pointing to some part of it, not the whole thing, so that
does mean that the stomach or the head or the left-pinkie fingernail atom
one billion atoms away from the left side touching the flesh of the finger
is you! Oh, but I don't understand an inherent collection, right?
Well, fine, so you think you're the inherently existent collection as measured
from the moment of your conception to the moment of your death and all
relations withing it. But what does that say about the things that
influenced you, for example the milkshake you drank awhile ago? Does
that milkshake exist as part of your continuum? Oh, only the parts
that your body absorbed? Well, what about the waste product, that
wasn't part of your body for a while, in your stomach and then intestines?
Some people would consider the contents of
the stomach to be part of your body, but maybe you do not. The nutrients
you absorbed are the only part that you kept, right? Well, how about
that atom mentioned earlier in your fingernail? It was obtained for
the now dead cell it is enclosed in from another milkshake long ago.
What happens when it gets clipped off? It is still part of you?
You exist at the same time, it is still part of you, and lying on the ground,
and then a dog comes along and eats it and absorbs some of the nutrients
into its body. Then you are a dog too? Oh, I'm sorry, I rushed
things a bit, you say it's not part of you and is cast off material.
Hair and fingernails are dead matter, right... Well, at one point
they were live cells and were part of you, much as your skin is.
Your skin dies, dries and falls off too, and I don't think you want to
say that your skin is not part of you. So you want to redefine yourself
as the mere collection of parts currently living at the time of analysis
in your body and all relationships between them along with your mind, as
time goes from conception to death. Parts that were you once don't
have to continue to be if they don't contribute to the current being at
the time of analysis, such as a cut off finger, or your father's sperm
before your conception. Well, I would think that this limits you
to being a predetermined being, if your future actions can be accounted
for already, because they are part of an inherently existent you, and you're
just blindly living the future as it unfolds. Try pointing at that
as yourself!
I continually get more and more confused as
I try to understand where or what you are, and it seems like your definition
of yourself is changing constantly; if you were inherently, pointably existent,
the definition would get clearer as one probed for it. If you were
an inherently existent thing, how could your definition change? Oh,
right your mind is on this set track of unfolding understanding into the
future, and the future mind understands itself differently perhaps than
the past did. Or maybe it is impossible for one to totally know oneself,
and one has no hope of really understanding what he is. What a copout,
and an excuse not to try and figure out what you are! If you really
believe that, our conversation is meaningless, but we both began because
you believed you were inherently existent. If it was impossible to
know yourself really, it would be pointless to believe yourself to be inherently
existent, because it wouldn't really be you.
Let's go back to the set duration idea you
cooked up. Do you really believe that you are just this duration
from conception to death? If not, I have at least convinced you that
you don't inherently exist in that way, and I challenge you to find yourself.
If you still do propose this, then what will happen already has, right?
I have two questions in my mind, and will ask only one. You don't
see a possibility there of a split in the time stream, one depending on
my asking the first question and one depending on the other? Okay,
maybe not. Well, then I still have a problem with the idea that you
could know yourself to be this self, because you don't know which question
I will ask--yet--and so do not know your future self, and cannot do other
than guess that this future self is you without knowing the full extent
of you (that is what happens in the future as well as what happened in
the past). If you had a gift of total pre-cognition, which is the
only way I see that you can claim to know enough about yourself to know
what you are, and you knew everything that you would do, everything you
would be, in the future, then you have no free will at all. You know
what you will do, so why do anything? Also, if you had this gift,
what would happen if you decided not to do something, by just lying down
and not doing it? If you can't do that, then someone else is pulling
your strings and you're not really you. If you can do that, then
you have not really got pre-cognition, and are again incapable of knowing
the totality of yourself to make a judgement as to who you are.
Wait a minute, you say? Why can't you
know enough about yourself to guess that you are the whole continuum (1),
or even are just the continuum so far to this point (2)? Well, the
second one's easier--if you are the continuum up to this point (2), then
who am I talking to in this part of the sentence? The you that you
are is back there where/when you agreed that you were this you. Time
marches on, if it exists at all. This is the problem; that you are
changing, and cannot be inherently the way you appear. The conception
to death continuum idea was all that preserved you from this problem at
the beginning of this debate, don't try and drop that now.
Back to the idea that you can guess about
what you don't know yet (1), or that you are the whole continuum and just
haven't been revealed yet in your future moments, and that you know you
are this whole continuum because you are making an intuitive leap--you
don't need to know your future to know that you will be in the future.
This still locks you into fatalistic predetermination, by the way, but
maybe you like the idea that you can't screw up your life because from
some viewpoint your life has already happened. This still leaves
the major problem of WHERE ARE YOU? If you (all of you) can point
to yourself, then you are pointing at the finger pointing at itself as
well, and have to point at the finger pointing at that finger, and so on
until you run out of fingers (not to mention the one I cut off earlier).
This is an infinitely recursive sequence, where your boundary of pointing
must keep expanding to point at the pointing. You never claimed to
be an infinite being, did you? I just wanted to leave something for
you to think about. Besides, all I wanted was your wallet anyway,
hand it over! Don't even think about the unfindability of your money.
I'm Honored, I Guess...
Winner on April 16 1998.